|
Lecture 11
Free Agency and the Will
by R. L. Dabney
UT is man a free agent?
Many have denied it. These may be ranked under two classes,
Theological Fatalists and Sensualistic Necessitarians. The former
argue from the doctrine of God's foreknowledge and providence; the
latter from the certainty, or, as it has unluckily been termed,
necessity of the Will. Say the one party; God has foreknown and
foreordained all that is done by rational man, as well as by
irrational elements, and His almighty providence infallibly
effectuates it all. Therefore, man's will is only seemingly free; he
must be a machine; compelled by God (for if God had no efficacious
means to compel, He could not certainly have foreknown) to do what
God purposed from eternity: and, therefore, man never had any real
choice; he is the slave of this divine fate. Say the other party,
headed by Hobbes: man's volitions are all effects: following with a
physical necessity upon the movement of the preponderant desires. But
what are his desires? The soul intrinsically is passive; the
attributes are nothing but certain susceptibilities of being affected
in certain ways, by impressions from without. There is nothing, no
thought, no feeling in the mind, except what sensation produced
there; indeed all inward states are but modified sensations. Hence,
desire is but the reflex of the perception of a desirable object;
resentment but the Reformed-action from impact. Man's emotions, then,
are the physical results of outward impressions, and his volitions
the necessary effects of his emotions. Man's whole volitions,
therefore, are causatively determined from without. While he supposes
himself free, he is the slave of circumstances: of fate, if those
circumstances arise by chance.
Now, in answer to all this, it would be
enough to say, that our consciousness contradicts it. There can be no
higher evidence than that of consciousness. Every man feels conscious
that wherever he has power to do what he wills, he acts freely. And
the validity of this uniform, immediate testimony of consciousness,
as Cousin well remarks, on this subject, must, in a sense, supersede
all other evidence of our free-agency; because all possible premises
of such. arguments must depend on the testimony of consciousness. But
still it is correct to argue, that man must be a free agent; because
this is inevitably involved in his responsibility. Conscience tells
us we are responsible for our moral acts. Reason pronounces,
intuitively, that responsibility would be absurd were we not free
agents. It may be well added, that when you approach revealed
theology, you find the Scriptures, (which so frequently assert God's
decree and providence,) assert and imply, with equal frequency, man's
free-agency. The king of Babylon (Isaiah 14) fulfills God's purpose
in capturing the sinful Jews; but he also fulfills the purpose of his
own heart. But we can do more than rebut the Fatalist's views by the
testimony of our consciousness; we can expose their sophistry. God's
mode of effectuating His purposes as to the acts of free agents, is
not by compelling their acts or wills, contrary to their preferences
and dispositions; either secretly or openly; but by operating through
their dispositions. And as to the latter argument, from the certainty
of the will; we repudiate the whole philosophy of sensationalism,
from which it arises. True, volitions are effects; but not effects of
the objects upon which they go forth. The perception of these is but
the occasion of their rise, not the cause. When desire attaches
itself upon any external object, terminating in volition, the whole
activity and power are in the mind, not in the object. The true
immediate cause of volition is the mind's own previous view and
feeling; and, this, again is the result of the minds' spontaneity, as
guided by its own prevalent attributes and habitudes.
What constitutes man a free agent? Say
one party: the self-determining power of the will; say the other: the
self-determining power of the soul. The one asserts that our acts of
volition are uncaused phenomena, that the will remains in equilibrio,
after all the preliminary conditions of judgment in the
understanding, and emotion of the native dispositions are fulfilled,
and that the act of choice is self-determined by the will, and not by
the preliminary states of soul tending thereto; so that volitions are
in every case, more or less contingent. The other party repudiates,
indeed, the old sensational creed, of a physical tie between the
external objects which are the occasions of our judgments and
feelings; and attributes all action of will to the soul's own
spontaneity as its efficient source. But it asserts that this
spontaneity, like all other forces in the universe, acts according to
law; that this law is the connection between the soul's own states
and its own choices, the former being as much of its own spontaneity
as the latter; that therefore volitions are uncaused, but always
follow the actual state of judgment and feeling, (single or complex)
at the time being; and that this connection is not contingent, but
efficient and certain. And this certainty is all that they mean by
moral necessity.
The latter is evidently the true
doctrine: because, (a) Our consciousness says so. Everyman feels that
when he acts, as a thinking being, he has a motive for acting so; and
that if he had not had, he would not have done it. The man is
conscious that he determines himself, else, he would not be free; but
he is equally conscious that it is himself judging and desiring,
which determines himself choosing: (b) Otherwise there would be no
such thing as a recognition of character, or permanent principles.
For there would be no efficient influence of the man's own principles
over his actions; (and it is by his actions alone we would know his
principles;) and his principles might be of a given character, and
his actions of a different, or of no character. (c) Consequently
there would be no certain result from human influence over man's
character and actions, in education and moral government. We might
educate the principles, and still fail to educate the actions and
habits. The fact which we all experience every day would be
impossible, that we can cause our fellow-men to put forth certain
volitions, that we can often do it with a foreseen certainty, and
still we feel that those acts are free and responsible. (d) Otherwise
man might be neither a reasonable nor a moral being. Not reasonable,
because his acts might be wholly uncontrolled at last by his whole
understanding; not moral, because the merit of an act depends on its
motive, and his acts would be motiveless. The self-determined
volition has its freedom essentially in this, according to its
advocates; that it is caused by no motive. Hence, no acts are free
and virtuous, except those which a man does without having any reason
for them. Is this good sense? Does not the virtuousness of a man's
acts depend upon the kind of reason which moved to them? (e) In the
choice of one's summum bonum, the will is certainly not contingent.
Can a rational being choose his own misery, apprehended as such, and
eschew his own happiness, for their own sakes? Yet that choice is
free; and if certainty is compatible with free-agency in this the
most important case, why not in any other? (f) God, angels, saints in
glory, and the human nature of Jesus Christ, must be certainly
determined to right volitions by the holiness of their own natures,
and in all but the first case by the indwelling grace and the
determinate purpose of God. So, on the other hand, lost souls, and
those who on earth have sinned away their day of grace, must be
certainly determined to evil, by their own decisive evil natures and
habits: yet their choice is free in both cases.
(g) If the will were contingent, there
could be no scientia media, and we should be compelled to the low and
profane ground of the Socinian; that God does not certainly foreknow
all things and in the nature of things, cannot. For the definition of
scientia media is, that it is that contingent knowledge of what free
agents will do in certain foreseen circumstances, arising out of
God's infinite insight into their dispositions. But if the will may
decide in the teeth of that foreseen disposition, there can be no
certain knowledge how it will decide. Nor is the evasion suggested by
modern Arminians (vide, Mansel's Lim. of Relig. Thought) of ally
force; that it is incompetent for our finite understandings to say
that God cannot have this scientia media, because we cannot see how
He is to have it. For the thing is not merely among the
incomprehensible, but the impossible. If a thing is certainly
foreseen, it must be certain to occur, or else the foreknowledge of
its certain occurrence is false. But if it is certain to occur, it
must be because there will be an antecedent, certainly, or
efficiently connected with the event, as cause. It is, therefore, in
the knowledge of this causal connection, that God would find his
scientia media, if this branch of His knowledge were mediate. To sum
up in a word, the inutility of this evasion, this Semi-Pelagian
theory begins by imputing to God an inferential knowledge of man's
free acts, and then, in denying the certain influence of motives
takes away the only ground of inference. (h) Last, God would have no
efficient means of governing free agents; things would be perpetually
emerging through their contingent acts, unforeseen by God, and across
His purposes; and His government would be, like man's, one of sorry
expedients to patch up His failures. Nor could He bestow any certain
answer to prayer, either for our own protection against temptation
and wrong choice, or the evil acts of other free agents. All the
predictions of Scripture concerning events in which the free moral
acts of rational agents enter as second causes, are arguments against
the contingency of the will. But we see striking instances in Joseph,
the Assyrians, Cyrus, and especially the Jews who rejected their
Lord. From this point of view, the celebrated argument of Edwards for
the certainty of the will from God's foreknowledge of creatures' free
acts, is obvious. The solution of the cavils attempted against it is
this position: That the principle, "No event without a cause," which
is, to us, a universal and necessary first truth, is also a truth to
the divine mind. When God certainly foresees an act. He foresees it
as coming certainly out of its cause. Hence, I repeat, if the
foresight is certain, the causation must be efficient.
I have indicated, both when speaking of
fatalism and of the impossibility of a scientia media concerning a
contingent will, the argument for the certainty of the will contained
in the fact of God's sovereignty. If He is universal First Cause,
then nothing is uncaused. Such is the argument; as simple as it is
comprehensive. It cannot be taught that volitions are uncaused,
unless you make all free agents a species of gods, independent of
Jehovah's control. In other words, if His providence extends to the
acts of free agents, their volitions cannot be uncaused; for
providence includes control, and control implies power. The argument
from God's sovereignty is, indeed, so conclusive, that the
difficulty, with thinking minds, is not to admit it, but to avoid
being led by it to an extreme. The difficulty rather is, to see how,
in the presence of this universal absolute sovereignty, man can
retain a true spontaneity. I began by defining that, while the will
of man is not self-determining, his soul is. I believe that a free,
rational Person does properly originate effects; that he is a true
fountain of spontaneity, determining his own powers, from within, to
new effects. This is a most glorious part of that image of God, in
which he is created. This is free-agency! Now, how can this fact be
reconciled with what we have seen of God as absolute First Cause?
(j) The demonstration may be closed by
the famous Reductio ad absurdum, which Edwards has borrowed from the
scholastics. If the will is not determined to choice by motives, but
determines itself, then the will must determine itself thereto by an
act of choice; for this is the will's only function. That is, the
will must choose to choose. Now, this prior choice must be held by
our opponents to be self-determined. Then it must be determined by
the will's act of choiceI. e., the will must choose to choose to
choose. Thus we have a ridiculous and endless regressus.
I now return to consider the objections
usually advanced against our doctrine. The most formidable is that
which shall be first introduced; the supposed incompatibility of
God's sovereignty as universal First Cause, with man's freedom.
The reconciliation may and does
transcend our comprehension, and yet be neither unreasonable nor
incredible. The point where the little circle of creature volition
inosculates with the immense circle of the divine will, is beyond
human view. When we remember that the wisdom, power and resources of
God are infinite, it is not hard to see that there may be a way by
which our spontaneity is directed, omnipotently, and yet without
infringement of its reality. The sufficient proof is, that we, finite
creatures, can often efficaciously direct the free will of our
fellows, without infringing it. Does any one say that still, in every
such case, the agent, if free as to us, has power to do the opposite
of what we induce him to do? True, he has physical power. But yet the
causative efficacy of our means is certain; witness the fact that we
were able certainly to predict our success. A perfect certainty, such
as results from God's infinitely wise and powerful providence over
the creature's will, is all that we mean by moral necessity. We
assert no other kind of necessity over the free will. More mature
reflection shows us, that so far are God's sovereignty and providence
from infringing man's free-agency, they are its necessary conditions.
Consider: What would the power of choice be worth to one if there
were no stability in the laws of nature; or no uniformity in its
powers? No natural means of effectuating volitions would have any
certainty, whence choice would be impotent, and motives would cease
to have any reasonable weight. Could you intelligently elect to sow,
if there were no ordinance of nature insuring seed time and harvest?
But now, what shall give that stability to nature? A mechanical,
physical necessity? That results in naught but fatalism. The only
other answer is: it must be the intelligent purpose of an almighty,
personal God.
The leading objections echoed by
Arminians against the certainty of the will, is, that if man is not
free from all constraint, whether of motive or co-action, it is
unjust in God to hold him subject to blame, or to command to those
acts against which His will is certainly determined, or to
punishments for failure. We reply, practically, that men are held
blamable and punishable for acts to which their wills are certainly
determined, both among men and before God; and all consciences
approve. This is indisputable, in the case of those who are
overmastered by a malignant emotion, as in Gen. 37:4, of devils and
lost souls, and of those who have sinned away their day of grace. The
Arminian rejoins,(Watson, vol. 2, p. 438:) Such transgressors,
notwithstanding their inability of will, are justly held responsible
for all subsequent failures in duty, because they sinned away the
contingency of their own wills, by their own personal, free act,
after they became intelligent agents. But as man is born in this
inability of will, through an arrangement with a federal head, to
which he had no opportunity to dissent, it would be unjust in God to
hold him responsible, unless He had restored the contingency of will
to them lost in Adam, by the common sufficient grace bestowed through
Christ. But the distinction is worthless: 1st, because, then, God
would have been under an obligation in righteousness, to furnish a
plan of redemption: but the Scriptures represent His act therein as
purely gracious. 2d. Because, then, all the guilt of the subsequent
sins of those who had thrown away the contingency of their own wills;
would have inhered in the acts alone by which they lost it. True;
that act would have been an enormously guilty one; the man would have
therein committed moral suicide. But it would also be true that the
man was thereafter morally dead, and the dead cannot work. 3d. The
Arminian should, by parity of reason, conclude, that in any will
certainly determined to holiness, the acts are not meritorious,
unless that determination resulted from the being's own voluntary
self-culture, and formation of good dispositions and habits.
Therefore God's will, which has been from eternity certainly
determined to good, does nothing meritorious! [*]
But the more analytical answer to this
class of objections is: that the certainty of disobedience in the
sinner's will is no excuse for him, because it proceeds from a
voluntary causei.e., moral disposition. As the volition is only the
man willing, the motive is the man feeling; it is the man's self.
There is no lack of the requisite capacities, if the man would use
those capacities aright. Now, a man cannot plead the existence of an
obstacle as his excuse, which consists purely in his own spontaneous
emission of opposition.
Now, the objections most confidently
urged, are: (a.) That our view makes man a machine, an intelligent
one, indeed; but a machine in which choice follows motive by a
physical tie. Ans. Man is in one sense a machine, (if you will use so
inappropriate an illustration); his spontaneous force of action has
its regular laws. But he is not a machine, in the essential point;
the motive power is not external, but is in himself.
(b) It is objected that our scheme fails
to account for all choices where the man acts against his own better
judgment and prevalent feelings; or; in other words, that while the
dictate of the understanding as to the truly preferable, is one way,
the will acts the other way; e. g., the drunkard breaks his own
anxiously made resolutions of temperance, and drinks. I reply, No;
still the man has chosen according to what was the prevalent view of
his judgment and feelings, as a whole, at the time. That drunkard
does judge sobriety the preferable part in the end, and on the whole;
but as to the question of this present glass of drink, (the only
immediate object of volition,) his understanding is misinformed by
strong propensity and the delusive hope of subsequent reform,
combining the advantages of present indulgence with future impunity;
so that its judgment is, that the preferable good will be this one
glass, rather than present, immediate self-denial.
(c) It is objected that our repentance
for having chosen wrong, always implies the feeling that we might
have chosen otherwise, had we pleased. I reply, Yes; but not unless
that choice had been preceded at the time by a different view of the
preferable. The thing for which the man blames himself is, that he
had not those different feelings and views. (d.) It is objected that
our theory could never account for a man's choosing between two
alternative objects, equally accessible and desirable, inasmuch as
the desire for either is equal, and the will has no self-deter-
mining power. The answer is, that the equality of objects by no means
implies the equality of subjective desires. For the mind is never in
precisely the same state of feeling to any external object or
objects, for two minutes together, but ever ebbing and flowing more
or less. In this case, although the objects remain equal, the mind
will easily make a difference, perhaps an imaginary one. And farther:
the two objects being equal, the inertia of will towards choosing a
given one of them, may be infinitesimally small; so that an
infinitesimally small preponderance of subjective motive may suffice
to overcome it. Remember, there is already a subjective motive in the
general, to choose some one of them. A favorite instance supposed is
that of a rich man, who has in his palm two or three golden guineas,
telling a beggar that he may take any one. But they are exactly equal
in value. Now, the beggar has a very positive motive to take some one
of them, in his desire for the value to him of a guinea. The least
imaginative impulse within his mind is enough to decide a supposed
difference which is infinitesimal.
Most important light is thrown upon the
subject, by the proper answer to the question, what is motive? The
will not being, as we have seen, self-moved, what is it which
precedes the volition, and is the true cause? I reply, by
distinguishing between motive and inducement. The inducement is that
external object, towards which the desire tends, in rising to choice.
Thus, the gold seen by the thief is the inducement to his volition to
steal. But the perception of the gold is not his motive to that
volition. His motive is the cupidity of his own soul, projecting
itself upon the gold. And this cupidity, (as in most instances of
motive,) is a complex of certain conceptions of the intellect, and
concupiscence of the heart; conceptions of various utilities of the
gold, and concupiscence towards the pleasures which it could procure.
The inducement is objective; the motive is subjective. The inducement
is merely the occasion, the motive is the true cause of the resulting
volition. The object which is the inducement projects no force into
the thief's soul. On the contrary, it is the passive object of a
force of soul projected upon it. The moral power is wholly from
within out wards. The action is wholly that of the thief's soul, the
inducement is only acted on. The proof of this all important view is
in this case. The same purse of gold is seen, in the same
circumstances of opportunity and privacy, by two men; the second is
induced by it to steal; on the first, it had no such power. Why the
difference? The difference must be subjective in the two men, because
objectively, the two cases are identical. Your good sense leads you
to explain the different results by the differing characters of the
two men. You say: "It is because the first man was honest, the second
covetous." That is to say, the causative efficiency which dictated
the two volitions was, in each case, from within the two men's souls,
not from the gold. Besides, the objects of sense are inert, dead,
senseless, and devoid of will. It is simply foolish to conceive of
them as emitting a moral activity. The thief is the only agent in the
case.
This plain view sheds a flood of light
on the doctrine of the will. A volition has always a cause, which is
the (subjective) motive. This cause is efficient, otherwise the
effect, volition, would not follow. But the motive is subjective; I.
e., it is the agent judging and desiring, just as truly as the
volition is the agent choosing. And this subjective desire, causative
of the choice, is a function of the agent's activity, not of his
passivity. The desire is as much of the agent's spontaneity
(self-action) as is the choosing. Thus is corrected the monstrous
view of those who deduced a doctrine of the necessity of the will
from a sensualistic psychology. If volition is efficiently caused by
desire, and if desire is but the passive reflex of objective
perception, then, indeed, is man a mere machine. His seeming
free-agency is wholly deceptive; and his choice is dictated from
without. Then, indeed, the out-cry of the semi-Pelagian against such
a necessity is just. But inducement is not motive; desire is an
activity, and not a passivity of our souls. Our own subjective
judgments and appetencies cause our volitions.
On the other hand, it is equally plain,
that the adaptation of any object to be an inducement to volition,
depends on some subjective attribute of appetency in the agent. This
state of appetency is a priori to the inducement, not created by it,
but conferring on the object its whole fitness to be an inducement.
In other words, when we seek to propagate a volition, by holding out
an inducement as occasion, or means, we always presuppose in the
agent whom we address, some active propensity. No one attempts to
allure a hungry horse with bacon, or a hungry man with hay. Why!
Common sense recognizes in each animal an a priori state of appetite,
which has already determined to which of them the bacon shall be
inducement, and to which the hay. The same thing is true of the
spiritual desires, love of applause, of power, of justice, &c. Hence,
it follows, that inducement has no power whatever to revolutionize
the subjective states of appetency natural to an agent. The effect
cannot determine its own cause.
From this point of view may also be seen
the justice of that philosophy of common sense, with which we set
out; when we remarked that every one regarded a man's free acts as
indices of an abiding or permanent character. This is only because
the abiding appetencies of soul decide which objects shall be, and
which shall not, be inducements to choice.
The student will perceive that I have
not used the phrase, "freedom of the will." I exclude it, because
persuaded that it is inaccurate, and that it has occasioned much
confusion and error. Freedom is properly predicated of a person, not
of a faculty. This was seen by Locke, who says, B. 2, ch. 21, sec.
10, "Liberty is not an idea belonging to volition, or preferring, but
to the person having the power. This is so obviously true, as to need
no argument. I have preferred therefore to use the phrase, at once
popular and exact: "free agency," and "free agent" Turretin (Loc. x,
Qu. I) sees this objection to the traditionary term, "Liberum
arbitrium," and hesitates about its use. But, after carefully
defining it, he concedes to custom that it may be cautiously used, in
the stipulated sense of the freedom of the Agent who wills. It would
have been safer to change it.
I have also preferred to state and argue
the old question as to the nature of free agency, in the common form
it has borne in the history of theology, before I embarrassed the
student with any of the attempted modifications of the doctrine.
Locke, following the sensualistic definition, says that "liberty is
the idea of a power in any agent to do or forbear any particular
action, according to the determination or thought of the mind." But
more profound analysts, as Reid and Cousin, saw that it consists in
more than the sensualist would represent: mere privilege to execute
outwardly what we have willed. My consciousness insists, that I am
also a free Agent in having that volition. There, is the essential
feature of choice; there, the rational preference first exhibits
itself. The rational psychologists, consequently, assert the great,
central truth, that the soul is self-determining. They see clearly
that the soul, and not the objective inducement, is the true cause of
its own acts of choice; and that hence man is justly responsible. But
in order to sustain this central point, they vacillate towards the
old Semi-Pelagian absurdity, that not only the man, but the separate
faculty of will, is self-determined. They fail to grasp the real
facts as to the nature and the power of subjective motive, the
exercise of another set of faculties in the soul.
Edwards saw more perspicaciously. Teaching that motive efficaciously
determines the will, he defined motive, as all that which, together,
moves the will to choice. It is always a complex of some view or
judgment of the understanding, and some movement of appetency or
repulsion as to an object. These two elements must be, at least
virtually and implicitly, in the precedaneous state of soul; or
choice, volition, would not result. The intelligence has seen some
object in the category of the true (or at least has thought it saw it
thus), and the appetency has moved towards it as in the category of
the desirable; else, no deliberate, affirmative volition had
occurred. The mere presence and perception of the object is the
occasion; the soul's own judgment and appetency form the cause of the
act of choice.
But what is appetency? If we conformed
it with passion, with mere impression on natural sensibilities, we
again fall into the fatal errors of the sensualist. Sir Wm. Hamilton
has done yeoman's service to truth, by illustrating the difference
(while he has claimed more than due credit for originating the
distinction). He separates the passive powers of "sensibility," from
the active powers of "conation." This is but the old (and correct)
Calvinistic classification of the powers of the soul under
"understanding," "affections," and will." Here, be it noted, the word
"will" is taken, as in some places of our Confession, in a much wider
sense than the specific faculty of choice. "Will" here includes all
the active powers of the soul, and is synonymous with Sir Wm.
Hamilton's "conative" powers. When we say, then, that man's soul is
self-determining, we mean that, in the specific formation of choice,
the soul choosing is determined by a complex of previous functions of
the same soul seeing and desiring. In this sense the soul is free.
But, as has been stated, no cause in the universe acts lawlessly.
"Order is heaven's first law."
And the regulative law of souls, when causing volitions, is found in
their dispositions. This all important fact in free-agency, is what
the scholastic divines called Habitus (not Consuetudo). It is the
same notion popularly expressed by the word character. We know that
man has such habitus, or disposition, which is more abiding than any
access, or one series of acts of any one desire. For we deem that in
a knave, for instance, evil disposition is present while he is
eating, or laughing, or asleep, or while thinking anything else than
his knavish plans. If we will reflect, we shall see that we
intuitively ascribe disposition, of some sort, to every rational free
agent: indeed we cannot think such an object without it. God, angel,
demon, man, each is invariably conceived as having some abiding
disposition, good or bad. It is in this that we find the regulative
principle of the free-agency of all volition rises according to
subjective motive. Subjective motive arises (freely) according to
ruling subjective disposition. Disposition also is spontaneousits
very nature is to act freely. Here then, we have the two ultimate
factors of free agency; Spontaneity, Disposition, Here we are at the
end of all possible analysis. It is as vain to ask: "Why am I
disposed thus?" as to seek a prior root of my spontaneity. The fact
of my responsibility as a free agent does not turn on the answer to
the question: it turns on this: that the disposition, which is
actually my own will, regulates the rise freely of just the
subjective motives I entertain. Let the student ponder my main
argument (on pages 122 to 124) and he will see that in no other way
is the free agency of either God, angel, or sinner, to be construed
by us.
Dr. McCosh (Div. and Moral Gov. as cited
in the syllabus,) wrests the true doctrine in some degree. He calls
the will the "optative faculty," correctly distinguishing desire from
sensibility, (which he terms emotion.) But he erroneously confounds
appetency and volition together as the same functions of one power.
That this is not correct, is evinced by one short question: May not
the soul have two competing appetencies, and choose between them? We
must hold fast, with the great body of philosophers, to the fact,
that the power of decision, or choice, is unique, and not to be
confounded even with subjective desires. It is the executive faculty.
Dr. McCosh concedes that motive (as defined by Edwards) efficaciously
decides the will; but he then asserts, with Coleridge, that the will
determines motives. Conceding this, he has virtually surrendered his
doctrine to the Arminian, and gotten around to a literal
self-determination of the will. He seems to have been misled by an
inaccurate glimpse of the truth I stated on p. 102, that the
disposition determines a priori which sorts of objects shall be
inducements to it. There is a two-fold confusion of this profound and
important truth. Disposition is not the will; but a regulative
principle of the appetencies, or "optative" functions, through them
controlling the will. And, second, it is wholly another thing to say,
that this disposition decides which objects shall be inducements, the
occasions only of volitions; and to say with Dr. McCosh, that the
will chooses among the soul's own subjective motives, the verae
causae of the very acts of choice!
Dr. Isaac Watts, as is often stated,
attempted to modify the doctrine of the will, by supposing that we
had inverted the order of cause and effect. He deemed that we do not
choose an object because we have desired it; but that we desire it
because we have chosen it. In other words, he thought desire the
result, and not the forerunner of choice. This scheme obviously
leaves the question unanswered: How do volitions arise? And by
seeming to leave them without cause, he favors the erroneous scheme
of the Arminian. It is enough to say, that no man's consciousness,
properly examined, will bear out this position. Do we not often have
desires where, in consequence of other causes in the mind, we form no
volition at all? This question will be seen decisive.
Dr. Albert Taylor Bledsoe, in his Reply
to Edwards, Theodicy, and other essays, attempts to modify the
Arminian theory, without surrendering it. He is too perspicacious to
say, with the crowd of semi-Pelagians, that volitions are uncaused
results in the mental world; he knows too well the universality of
the great, necessary intuition, ex nihilo nihil. But denying that
motives, even subjective, are cause of acts of choice, he says the
mind is the immediate cause of them. He seems here to approach very
near the orthodox view. Even Dr. Alexander could say, while denying
the self-determination of the will, that he was ready to admit the
self-determination of the mind. But this concession of Dr. Bledsoe
does not bring him to the correct ground. It leaves the question
unexplained, in what way the mind is determined from within to
choice. It refuses to accept the efficient influence of subjective
motive. It still asserts that any volition may be contingent as to
its use, thus embodying the essential features of Arminianism. And
above all: it fails to see or admit the most fundamental fact of all;
that original disposition which regulates each being's desires and
volitions. The applications which this author makes of his modified
doctrine betray still its essential Arminianism.
In conclusion, it is only necessary at
this place to say in one word, that the disposition which is found in
every natural man, as to God and godliness, is depravity. Hence his
will, according to the theory expounded above, is, in the Scriptural
sense, in bondage to sin, while he remains properly a free and
responsible agent.
NOTE:
The antiquity of this cavil, and its proper refutation, may be seen in the Cur Deus Homo of Anselm, pt. 2, chap. 10, where the topic is the impeccability of Christ.
BOSO."I say, then, if He cannot sin,
because, as you say, He cannot wish to, He obeys from necessity;
whence, He is not righteous from the freedom of His will. Then, what
favour will be due Him for His righteousness? For we are wont to say,
that God, therefore, made angels and men such that they could sin;
since, inasmuch as they could forsake righteousness, and could keep
righteousness out of the freedom of their will, they would deserve
approbation and favour, which would not be due to them were they
righteous from necessity."
ANSELM."Are the (elect) angels who now
cannot sin, to be approved or not?"
BOSO."Of course they are, because this
gift (that they cannot sin) they earned in this way, viz.: by not
choosing to sin when they could."
ANSELM."Well, what do you say about
God, who is not able to sin, and yet did not earn that state by not
choosing to sin while He had the power to do it: isn't He to be
praised for His righteousness?"
BOSO."I wish you would answer for me
there; for, if I say He is not to be praised for it, I know I am
lying; but if I say He is, I am afraid I shall spoil that argument of
mine about the angels."
Anselm proceeds, accepting this virtual
confession of defeat, to explain: That the approvableness of the
angels' conduct depends, not on the question, "How they came by the
dispositions which prompt them to obey;" but on the question, whether
they have such dispositions, and act them out of their own accord:
That God, in creating them with free-agency, intelligence and holy
dispositions, conferred His own image upon them; and that their
spontaneity, though conferred, is as real, and as really moral, as
God's spontaneity, which was not conferred, but eternal and
necessary. And that, if there were any force in Boso's cavil, that a
morally necessitated righteousness would not be free and approvable
in the creature, it would be far stronger against God, whose holiness
is the most strictly necessitated of all, being absolutely eternal. (Return to text.)
Text scanned by Mike Bremmer
|